Some Thoughts on Sanity, Theology, and Change

Douglas P. McManaman
March 10, 2020
Reproduced with Permission

We speak of psychosis as a loss of contact with reality, either permanent or temporary; psychotic episodes, for instance, are temporary breaks with reality. There is a sense, however, that being out of touch with "reality" is a matter of degree. I contend that the more we come to understand the inductive nature of knowledge acquisition and its implications, we should begin to see that we are always, to some degree at least, out of touch with reality. All knowledge begins in sensation, as Aristotle maintained (nothing is in the intellect that is not first in the senses); in other words, our knowledge has empirical origins; this means it begins with evidence and proceeds towards the most coherent and consistent explanation of the evidence. Most importantly, however, although our grasp of the real expands continually - a or should - , the process of expansion is - or should be - accompanied by an awareness of an ever decreasing circle in the midst of which we find ourselves, and at the edge of which is a vast and expanding penumbra of obscurity. Leaving aside early or first-episode psychosis (FEP), the genuinely insane are typically unaware that they have lost contact with the real, but the most sane among us have the greatest awareness that in the final analysis, the reality they are in touch with is so much larger than is their current grasp of it - increasingly so - , and they have the greatest awareness that their current worldview, which cannot exceed the limited information they possess about the real, is in large measure the product of what they believe the world to be through the lens of that limited set of information. It is all too easy to confuse our worldview with the world, which we always know only deficiently.

The benefit of coming to a deeper appreciation of statistical reasoning and Bayesian inference [1] is that one begins to realize both how risky our intuitive and formal statistical inferences are, and how precarious are those estimates that are the product of Bayesian inference. Statisticians and research scientists tend to have a deeper appreciation of the risky nature of our current convictions. Their subject matter is very often data that is too large for us to manage with great precision, such as a population mean, which we can only estimate - along with its standard deviation - , on the basis of a sample.[2] The estimate, however, is typically an interval, and the wider the interval, the greater our confidence; the lesser our confidence level, the narrower and more precise that interval becomes. In other words, the more precise and thus more useful our estimates, the greater their vulnerability to error. Perhaps this is why good scientists tend not to speak with a rhetoric of high confidence, especially when our truth claims bear upon matters of precision. Only when matters become more general - and perhaps less useful - is greater confidence warranted.

Moreover, Bayesian inference should bring us to a greater awareness of the role that experience plays in knowledge acquisition.[3] The probability of a hypothesis given the evidence [p(H|E)] leaves us with a space of uncertainty (i.e., 0.49 or 0.70, etc.), and such inference depends upon a knowledge of base rates (for example, 48.2% of all Americans age 15+ are married, while 51.8% are not) and likelihoods (i.e., the probability that a couple has children given that they are married is 90%). However, when we estimate the probability of a belief given certain pieces of evidence, we tend to ignore base rates (prior ratios), and so our estimates that are the product of intuitive reasoning are often seriously mistaken - hence, we ought not to trust our intuitive probability estimates. The most important implication of Bayesian inference, however, is the effect that experience has on our posterior probabilities - new information changes them. And so, once again, we are reminded not to be too confident in what we claim to "know" - the very fact that new information that affects our base rates demands that we continually update our estimates, not to mention recognize them as estimates in the first place, and not "knowledge" per se.[4]

Our day to day reasoning, however, is not fundamentally mathematical, that is, we do not typically perform mathematical calculations on the basis of prior probabilities; rather, we reason on the basis of plausible data, not probabilities, and the reasoning is not calculative, but comparative. Sometimes what is improbable, i.e., that Jack was hit by a city bus, is moderately plausible given the plausibility indexes of our current data (witness statements, or a statement from the victim, or other sources, etc.), and often a number of competing but estimates are equally plausible.[5]

In terms of plausible reasoning, all we ever have at any one time are limited sets of data formulated in propositions having a degree of plausibility, either minimal, moderate, high, etc., that is, a less than certain character. The entire set of data at our disposal is typically overabundant and inconsistent. Indeed, there are many propositions in our data set, the truth of which we can be certain and from which we can deduce a great deal, rendering explicit what was previously implicit.[6] There are, however, a myriad of theses that are less than certain. The task of sound reasoning is to bring maximal consistency to this set of data.

What is particularly interesting to note is that bringing maximal consistency does not guarantee that in the end we possess the truth. What we have at best is the most plausible estimate given the information currently available. New information very often alters the consistency of our plausibilistically favored subsets of data bearing upon specific matters, with the result that a new estimate is in order. This is why there is a great deal of "mind-changing" in the sciences - we just don't know whether or not we have enough information at any one time to resolve a particular question with complete certitude. It seems, in fact, that we are always information deficient.

And so, once again, the worldview that results from our current set of information is an ever changing one, that is, an evolving worldview. It has always been a deficient worldview, because the information on the basis of which it is established at any given time is deficient. Even the little that we have at our disposal is a product of interpretation, and our interpretation is once again made up of risky inferences. As Feynman says of science, it is an ever expanding frontier of ignorance; similarly, our day to day knowing is precisely an ever expanding frontier of ignorance: the more we come to know about the world we live in, the more we should realize just how much more we did not know than we previously thought there was to know. With every new discovery comes a manifold of new questions, and new questions open up new and unexplored avenues that, when explored, provide new information that very often upsets the consistency of what we thought was a well-established conceptual framework, causing us to adjust our estimates by discarding data inconsistent with more plausible data in order to establish a different and plausibilistically favored subset of data from which a better and more accurate worldview may arise. Moreover, new information may inadvertently strengthen a position we've held for a time; however, a new and maximally plausible estimate is no guarantee that we are any closer to the truth - a previous but now plausibilistically less favored estimate may in fact be true, and time may reveal that. In other words, the most current estimate is not necessarily closer to the truth. That is why learning is very often an oscillating process; if a position or estimate is true, it is not necessarily the case that newer information will corroborate it; we may be taken further away from it, only to return to it at a later date. Progress, in other words, is not necessarily unidirectional.

What this implies is that we are always, in a manner of speaking, out of touch with reality, for reality is so much larger, inconceivably larger, than our current grasp of it, and the frontier of our ignorance is ever expanding. And although we are always relatively out of touch with the real, at least we can know that we are always relatively out of touch with it. That, I contend, is what distinguishes the sane from the insane - the insane are out of touch and have no awareness of the fact. I dare say, however, that most people believe their grasp of reality to be far more comprehensive that it can possibly be, for many speak with a rhetoric of certainty that assumes a knowledge that is just not humanly possible on a large number of issues, given the little time invested in those matters. What I am suggesting is that most people have a greater resemblance to the insane than they do to the genuinely sane; the former tend to resist this never-ending learning process that requires adjusting our estimates in the light of new information. The intellectual, for example, who works exclusively in the realm of ideas, who has little interest in testing those ideas before they are imposed on a society, has a greater resemblance to the insane than the sane, which is likely why intellectuals who succeed in having their untested albeit interesting ideas implemented on a wider social scale usually end up costing the taxpayer a great deal.

One irony in all of this is that a great deal of disordered confidence and resistance of the learning process is found within that discipline whose object is the mystery par excellence, the unutterable mystery of God. Many who are fond of theology fail to appreciate just how much the logic of the scientific method is involved in this more general science. Moral philosophy, for example, does not escape this logic, nor is this logic foreign to biblical exegesis and the study of Scripture, and thus by extension, moral theology or any other branch of sacred theology. Moral reasoning follows much the same law of complementarity that we encounter in statistics: the more universal or general the discourse, the greater the certainty, but as we move to greater precision, vulnerability to error increases. A fine example of this is Germain Grisez's Difficult Moral Questions (Franciscan Press, 1997). That volume was the product of years of thinking about principles and their application to specific moral problems that have arisen as a result of new circumstances. On a number of occasions, I had the privilege of observing Joseph Boyle's uncertainty as he pondered on the edge of the frontiers of a difficult moral problem. He refused to overstate his case, and he was all too aware that he may not have in his possession enough rational data necessary to satisfactorily work out the problem which preoccupied him at the time; moreover, these analytical moral philosophers (Grisez, Boyle, Finnis, etc.) have, over the years, changed their position on a number of important issues, thanks to more thought, dialogue, and discussion. We see the same inductive/investigative process in the area of biblical exegesis as well. With new historical data, what was once thought to be the case is now relegated to a lower level of plausibility while a more plausible hypothesis takes top spot.

Canon lawyers working on marriage tribunals, for example, judging cases on a team of 3, will testify that some cases are easy while others are very difficult; the latter are often resolved with a 2:1 ratio (the one outvoted has to humbly accept the majority decision, but after reviewing the reasons given will often see what was not noticed earlier). Those on the outside, unfamiliar with this process - and it is a process - , tend to have a difficult time appreciating the subtleties of these matters. Unlike judges who regularly work on such cases, most people have not encountered such intricate and murky situations, permeated as they are with uncertainty. A view from the "inside" - whether the subject matter is politics or law, etc. - is very different from a view from the "outside", and many on the outside are too emotionally invested to acknowledge their own deficiency of information and will proceed to dogmatically spout off on all sorts of issues they know very little about.

Pastoral approaches to spiritual direction magnifies this logic even further. A good pastor of souls must be able to pick up subtle clues in the words, gestures, and reactions of the directee, clues on the basis of which one may rapidly inference to information needed to find the best way to communicate important principles and insights that cannot be effectively imparted in the same way to everyone. A pastor of souls, like a good teacher, is one who is capable of detecting clues that give evidence of conditions within a person that render him/her temporarily incapable of understanding certain things, not to mention conditions that make possible a certain understanding. There is a distinction between a pastor of souls and a moral theologian. It is certainly possible for a person to be both, but a theologian without a good pastoral sensibility, that is, without a mind for contingent factors and other clues, is not someone who should be providing spiritual direction. To be avoided are the two extremes of the nonchalant progressive who confuses a pastoral sense with moral permissiveness on the one hand, and the hard-nosed conservative who has no sense of the complexities of the human person on the other.

There's no warrant for dogmatism here; what appears to be the "truth" at one time is eventually discovered to be a rather deficient position, or a position in need of further distinction. In the end, what this suggests is the need for a spirit of greater humility; it suggests the need for constant dialogue and the prudence of a listening posture. But this is precisely the posture lacking in a large sector of the current student environment, among professors of certain disciplines (especially the soft sciences), among the faithful who are passionately on the left and on the right, and among many of the clergy, both highly traditional and liberal. What makes these epistemic matters more difficult is the fact that character and mood play a significant role in knowledge acquisition. Character plays a fundamental role in our ability to make moral distinctions, among other things - people will not see what it is they are unwilling to see. Character is a more permanent epistemic condition, while mood is temporary. Both, however, beget blind spots.


.

.

.

Top